Gottlob Frege’s Impact on the Philosophy of Language

Frege considered his greatest work to be his contributions to mathematics, logic and science. Yet his contributions to the study and philosophy of language have proven even more enduring.

Jan 2, 2023By Luke Dunne, BA Philosophy & Theology
gottlob frege philosophy of language

 

Gottlob Frege is one of the most important and influential philosophers of the 20th century, and he is known perhaps above all for his contributions to the philosophy of language, the subsequent significance of which cannot be overstated. Michael Dummett, himself an extremely prominent and influential philosopher, studied Frege extensively. He argues that all of analytic philosophy, that which came to dominate English speaking universities in the 20th century and that which continues to dominate those universities today, owes its existence to Frege, so much so that Dummett himself refers to this tradition as ‘Post-Fregean Philosophy’.

 

Frege’s Greatest Achievement: Shifting the Focus on Language

gottlob frege grave cross
A photograph of Frege’s grave

 

Dummett holds that Frege’s crucial innovation was the focus on language, and above all meanings, as the basis of all philosophical activity.

 

“Before Descartes, it can hardly be said that any part of philosophy was recognized as being … fundamental to all the rest: the Cartesian revolution consisted in giving this role to the theory of knowledge …[, which] was accepted as the starting point for more than two centuries.”

 

“Frege’s basic achievement lay in the fact that he totally ignored the Cartesian tradition, and was able, posthumously, to impose his different perspective on other philosophers of the analytic tradition…. For Frege the first task, in any philosophical enquiry, is the analysis of meanings.”

 

frans hals portrait descates
Portrait of René Descartes by Frans Hals, 1649-1700, via Wikimedia Commons.

Get the latest articles delivered to your inbox

Sign up to our Free Weekly Newsletter

 

Dummett elsewhere claims that “We can, therefore, date a whole epoch in philosophy as beginning with the work of Frege, just as we can do with Descartes.” Frege’s work formed the basis for the work of Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein to found and shape many aspects of philosophy in the English speaking world.

 

What is Frege’s philosophy of language? Frege sets out the key components of his philosophy of language in the paper Sinn und Bedeutung. Although this paper is sometimes translated as ‘Sense and Reference’, due to controversy over the precise meaning of the term ‘bedeutung’, at least in terms of Frege’s usage of it, we will leave the latter term untranslated for now.

 

The paper starts by considering two puzzles of language through a certain view of language: that what language does, above all, is denote, represent or refer to objects. The first puzzle concerns identity statements; those statements which pose a relation of sameness between two things.

 

The Puzzle of Identity Statements

de morgan phosphorus hesperus
Phosphorus (Morning star) and Hesperus (Evening star) by Evelyn de Morgan, 1881, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

The crux of the puzzle concerns preserving the difference between identity relations of the form (a=b), where a and b are different names for the same thing, and (a=a), where a and a are the same name for the same thing. If all that language does is denote objects, then there isn’t any non-trivial difference between these things.

 

This seems implausible. Take the example of writers who write under a pseudonym, such as Samuel Clemens, who wrote all of his books under the name ‘Mark Twain’. We know that Samuel Clemens is Samuel Clemens just by examining the sentence; ‘Samuel Clemens is Samuel Clemens’. Indeed, it seems utterly trivial that Samuel Clemens is indeed Samuel Clemens. We cannot know that Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain just by examining the sentence ‘Samuel Clemens is Mark Twain’.

 

The second puzzle Frege is at least conceptually continuous with the first. It is to do with what are called ‘propositional attitude reports’.

 

franz hals descartes engraving
An engraving of Descartes, also by Frans Hal

 

The Puzzle of Propositional Attitude Reports 

photograph mark twain
A photograph of Mark Twain… (taken by A.F. Bradley in 1907, via the Library of Congress).

 

A propositional attitude is a psychological relation holding between a person and proposition. In the sentence ‘I believe x’, I am the person, x is the proposition, and ‘believe’ is the propositional attitude. Frege is concerned by how these kinds of sentences interact with a very intuitive principle which governs identity statements, known as the ‘Principle of Identity Substitution’.

 

The Principle of Identity substitution holds that, “If a certain name (n) appears in a true sentence S, and the identity sentence n = m is true, then the Principle of Identity Substitution tells us that the substitution of the name m for the name n in S does not affect the truth of S.”

 

However, the problem concerns those names which an individual does not know to denote or refer to the same thing. Let’s say that the Joker believes Batman is a crime fighting superhero. It is also true that Batman is Bruce Wayne. So does that mean that the Joker thinks that Bruce Wayne is a crime fighting superhero? No, because the Joker does not know that Batman and Bruce Wayner are one and the same person. We cannot substitute “Bruce Wayne” for “Batman” in all sentences while retaining their truth.

 

Frege’s Response to the Puzzles

samuel clemens photograph
…and a photograph of Samuel Clemens (taken by Napoleon Sarony in 1895, via the NY Public Library Digital Collections)

 

The strategy behind Frege’s response is clear. He wants to retain a picture of the world in terms of fairly simple entities, which are referred to by language, along with relations between them, which are also mapped by language (and that’s just about it, for language and reality).

 

He takes this simple picture and combines it with an additional concept to cover the problems which this simple theory of language generates. This concept is that of ‘sense’, which can account for the cognitive significance of a name or description. Sense is language as it is orientated towards the listener, the interpreter, the person who speaks and is spoken to, whereas Bedeutung is orientated towards reality.

 

This notion of sense, though extremely useful for Frege’s purposes, is far from straightforward. To illustrate one complication which is clear almost immediately, consider the word bachelor. If I don’t know what the word bachelor means, then I might not know that the word ‘bachelor’ and ‘unmarried man’ denote the same thing. But there is a difference between two things having different senses in this way, and two descriptions of the same thing having different senses not because I don’t know that they refer to the same object, but because they refer to the same object in a different manner.

 

The latter introduces notions of phrasing, of style, of the ‘way in which we say things’ rather than ‘what we say’ as such.

 

Defining the Philosophy of Language

illustration university jena
A 19th century illustration of the University of Jena, where Frege was a professor. Unknown author. Via Wikimedia Commons.

 

The philosophy of language, as it is practiced in most English speaking universities, would not exist without the approach to language pioneered by Frege. Before we can reflect on Frege’s philosophy of language any further, it is worth clarifying just what the philosophy of language is. What distinguishes the philosophy of language from, say, linguistics, which is also concerned with generating general theories about language and languages, and has its own way of framing problems of meaning?

 

There is no firm distinction between other ways of studying language and the philosophy of language, and this is common in many philosophical disciplines; the philosophy of mathematics cannot be strictly distinguished from mathematics itself, and indeed historically many great mathematicians are also great philosophers of mathematics.

 

Sometimes we can distinguish the philosophy of x from the subject x by distinguishing a specific technique of set of techniques which those who takes part in x tend to us; the philosophy of psychology is not, as a rule, itself a form of psychology, and we know this because psychologists of all kinds employ a range of technical instruments and skills which philosophers do not.

 

The Focus of the Philosophy of Language: Meaning 

gottingen frege memorial plaque
A plaque in commemoration of Frege, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

Much of the time, however, what distinguishes one area of philosophy both from other areas of philosophy and from other subjects are the concerns which happen to occupy the people who call themselves ‘philosophers of x’. These boundaries are incidental and fuzzy, and should correspondingly concern us mainly as historical distinctions rather than normative in any sense.

 

What are those concerns for philosophers of language? Colin McGinn, a prominent philosopher of language, begins by attempting to define the philosophy of language as concerned, above all, with meaning. Now, meaning itself requires some clarification, because it is a term which we put to a variety of different uses.

 

David Lewis, one of the major figures of the analytic tradition Frege helped found, draws a distinction between two different kinds of meaning in the following way: “first, the description of possible languages or grammars as abstract semantic systems whereby symbols are associated with aspects of the world; and, second, the description of the psychological and sociological facts whereby a particular one of these abstract semantic systems is the one used by a person or population. Only confusion comes of mixing these two topics.”

 

Some Assumptions About Meaning 

language flowers mucha
Language of Flowers by Alphonse Mucha, 1900, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

So, we can see that meaning refers both to the relationship between the world and language, and between the former kind of meaning and what is meaningful to particular people, integrated in a particular social context. McGinn, focuses on meaning in the former sense, and goes on to reframe this in terms of the question of how language hooks up to reality.

 

“Language is about the world – we use it to communicate about things. So we must ask what this ‘aboutness’ is: what is it and how does it work?”. There isn’t space here to investigate these assumptions too thoroughly, but there are a few objections which can be raised to conception of language and reality which will be useful when turning to Frege’s own theory of language.

 

It is far from clear what it is for something to be ‘about’ the world, and McGinn is surely right to identify this as worthy of investigation. There is a difference between ambiguity which we respond to by specification, and ambiguity we respond to with doubt. In the former case, one has already determined that ‘about the world’ is a genuine relation and what is required is a specification of just what it involves. In the latter case, we are taking the claim ‘language is about the world’ as itself up for debate, not just in need of refinement.

 

Frege’s Theory and the Relationship Between Reference and Reality 

gottingen marketplace town centre
A photograph of Gottingen, where Frege was a student, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

What is particularly important when we come to Frege’s theory is that McGinn’s picture of language and reality seems to suggest that objects are referrable in a straightforward way. Certain objects support this view of language more easily than others: the word apple relates to the crunchy, shiny, sweet thing I have in my hand more seamlessly than the words ‘but’ or ‘whenever’ relate to anything ‘in the world’.

 

Why should we accept, prima facie, that any acceptable use of ‘but’ or ‘whenever’ refers to a state which is ‘in the world’? It is not clear that all of the ways in which we deploy language can be made to fit with McGinn’s picture of language as a mirror, double or corollary of reality. It is equally unclear that every aspect of reality can be rendered in language; some things may simply be unsayable.

Author Image

By Luke DunneBA Philosophy & TheologyLuke is a graduate of the University of Oxford's departments of Philosophy and Theology, his main interests include the history of philosophy, the metaphysics of mind, and social theory.