Gottfried W. Leibniz: The Last True Genius

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was one of the most significant philosophers of the 17th century. His approach to (im)possibility, God, and evil have been deeply influential.

Dec 21, 2022By Luke Dunne, BA Philosophy & Theology
leibniz last genius philosopher

 

What was the philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz? This article will explore several of his contributions to philosophical logic and epistemology, as well as his concept of God through the lens of the defining concept of Leibnizian thought: that of Theodicy.

 

Leibniz is commonly regarded as the last ‘universal genius’, that is, one who can reasonably be said to have proficient knowledge of every or almost every field of intellectual endeavour in the time and place in which they lived. Denis Diderot’s oft-quoted description of Leibniz is worth quoting: ““Perhaps never has a man read as much, studied as much, meditated more, and written more than Leibniz… What he has composed on the world, God, nature, and the soul is of the most sublime eloquence. If his ideas had been expressed with the flair of Plato, the philosopher of Leipzig would cede nothing to the philosopher of Athens”.

 

The Life of Leibniz: Working With Others, Standing Alone

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Bernhard Christoph Francke
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz by Bernhard Christoph Francke, 1729, via Wikimedia commons

 

Leibniz was born in Leipzig, in the eastern part of modern-day Germany, and he was in turn a student and an academic at the local university. As with many philosophers of the time, he was much involved in political and diplomatic work – in his case, on behalf of the House of Hanover – which gave him ample opportunity to travel from his relatively isolated position in Leipzig and speak with other major intellectuals.

 

Leibniz spoke to Malebranche, Huygens, Spinoza and Pascal over the course of his lifetime. Based on extensive written correspondence, Leibniz’s work was a product of the increasingly interconnected European intellectual environment as well as one of individual genius when he was working in isolation. This European intellectual establishment was to turn its back on him after his death, in part due to a change in fashions (against system building and rationalism in philosophy, for instance) and in part due to a controversy of his claim to have discovered calculus independently of Newton.

 

Get the latest articles delivered to your inbox

Sign up to our Free Weekly Newsletter

Nevertheless, even prior to a positive reappraisal of his work in the 20th century, Leibniz has long been considered the third of the ‘great’ early modern philosophers, preceded by Descartes and Spinoza. Whereas Descartes sees metaphysics in the service of science, and Spinoza sees metaphysics in the service of ethics, for Leibniz metaphysics is a good in itself.

 

The value of metaphysics, for Leibniz, is that of striving to emulate God, who is capable of distinguishing sense from nonsense, the knowable from the unknowable, at all times and in all things. In other words, it is part of our nature as human beings to strive towards the most general kinds of understanding.

 

Everything Is Intelligible, Nothing Is Contradictory

leibniz illustration black white
Copper engraving (without signature) engraved by Martin Bernigeroth, 1710, with the bust of the polymath Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Via the Digital Library of the Herzog August Bibliothek

 

Yet, one consequence of Leibniz framing this in terms of our nature is that he felt that this general kind of understanding would make itself apparent to us as we are, grounded in a particular point of view. This is the crux of Leibniz’s epistemology.

 

That isn’t to say that knowledge is relative to that point of view – all knowledge is a priori – but our ability to know it is derived from our context and contextual relations. The relations of being a human being is one such relation, but so too are the relations involved in living in a certain intellectual culture, etc.

 

Leibniz assumes from the outset that things do in fact make sense – “nothing unintelligible happens” – and it is this which constitutes the first principle of Leibnizian philosophy, known as the ‘principle of sufficient reason’, which states that there is some intelligible reason for everything; for every state of being, for every event, every change.

 

The second principle of Leibnizian philosophy is the ‘principle of contradiction’ – ‘nothing can at the same time be and not be, but everything either is or is not’. It is easy to see why many commentators on Leibniz see these principles as delineating the space of metaphysics by drawing a boundary. The principle of sufficient reason certifies success within, the principle of contradiction exposes failure without.

 

Introducing Theodicy

frans hals descartes portrait
Portrait of René Descartes by Frans Hals, 1649-1700, via Wikimedia Commons

 

Like Descartes, Leibniz’s approach to metaphysics has a strong religious element. Leibniz is well known for his attempt at a theodicy, and his use of possibility and necessity to generate said theodicy. A theodicy is a response to the problem of evil, which is a philosophical problem that emerges for those who believe in a certain kind of deity: one who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent.

 

For many who hold the Abrahamic faiths – that is, for many Christians, Muslims and Jews – these are implicitly or explicitly essential features of God (although this is not uniformly so, and certain theodicies attempt to limit or do away with one of these qualities).

 

The problem of evil can be formulated as follows: why is there evil in the world, when God knows everything (and so knows that there is evil, where there is evil, how to prevent evil), God can do everything (and so could prevent evil), and God is all loving (and so, presumably, despises evil just as any loving creature does)?

 

leipzig photograph modern day
View over the inner city of Leipzig with Thomaskirche, via Wikimedia Commons.

 

A theodicy is any theory which attempts to answer the challenge posed by the problem of evil to belief in God. Leibniz’s argument is this: God is responsible for all that is contingently the case, which means – at least in Leibniz’s terminology – God is responsible for the instantiation of the world. The actual world, meaning the one we are in now, is one of various possible worlds.

 

However, God’s nature ensures that whatever “God knows through his wisdom, chooses through his goodness, and produces through his power” is the best that there could possibly be, and so we must live not in just one of various possible worlds, but in the best of all possible worlds. 

 

An intriguing ambiguity is that whereas the evil in the problem of evil is normally understood as a kind of moral evil, or at least evil which can be assessed in moral terms, that is not the sense in which Leibniz conceives of our world as being the ‘best’. Goodness, and so the superlative quality of goodness which is for something to be the ‘best’, relates not to any particular conception of goodness but to a form of goodness which is intrinsic to the form of reality. This is not, at least in any straightforward sense, the conception of goodness which corresponds to the evil we have in mind when the problem of evil is raised.

 

Natural Evil and Human Evil

Christiaen Huygens II (1629 1695), by Caspar Netscher
Christiaan Huygens, the astronomer by Gaspar Netscher, 1671.

 

Whether or not atrocities are part of the order of things does not seem to be directly relevant to our assessment of whether they are evil. Yet on the other hand, whether some thing counts as an instance of evil does seem to at least partly involve some assessments about the status of that thing within wider structures of reality. Although natural disasters are often referred to as ‘natural evil’ in the context of theodicy and the problem of evil, there is clearly a sense in which natural disasters are not evil in the way that human evil is.

 

Perhaps that sense is partly informed by the fact that any individual instance of them is a terrible thing, that natural disasters happen at all is a necessary component of certain weather, tectonic and oceanic processes functioning, and it is their functioning in the way they do which makes life possible in the first place. Clearly, this isn’t the only reason to distinguish between human evil and natural evil, but it might go some way to understanding what Leibniz has in mind when he argues that our world, in spite of the many instances of evil, is nonetheless the best of all possible worlds.

 

The Basic Datum Argument and the Limits of Ethical Discourse

irenaeus statue lyon
Statue of Irenæus of Lyon by Carl Rohl Smith, 1883-84, Frederikskirken, København. Image via Wikimedia Commons.

 

The problem of theodicy – both posed in terms of whether theodicy is possible, and in terms of what a plausible theodicy would have to prove – is an old one. The very earliest Christian theorists – most prominently St Augustine and St Irenaeus – were deeply concerned with the problem of evil, and it has inspired an enormous quantity of philosophical and theological discussion. Therefore, it is easy to lose sight of the very simplicity of the most basic argument against the possibility of theodicy.

 

As Adrian Moore puts it: “The existence of better possible worlds seems itself to be a basic datum, impinging on us every bit as forcefully as any principle to the effect that things always make sense – nay, through our various trials and afflictions, altogether more forcefully”.

 

“To reject that datum is not merely to invite scepticism about whatever reasoning has brought us to do so. It is to invite accusations of intellectualist insensibility. It is to risk making a mockery of our very real, very unmockable suffering”.

 

It is possible to still further, and expand the notion of the ‘basic datum’ into an argument about the conceivability of ethical discourse. If we accept Leibniz’s claim – that we live in the best of all possible worlds – what then are the consequences of this upon those ethical claims which involve attempts to change the world in some way or other? Ethical discourse, insofar as it is normative – that is, it seeks to influence the way people behave – seems to suppose at least the possibility that we do not live in the best of all possible worlds.

 

Teleology and Ethical Discourse Within Leibniz’s Conception

guercino god angel
God the Father and Angel by Guercino, 1620, via Google Arts & Culture.

 

Accepting Leibniz’s view might not preclude the possibility of ethical discourse as such, but would presumably alter our conception of change such that before any improvement is made, before any kind of unnecessary suffering can be limited or eradicated, the world itself must change.

 

In short, this would force us to conceive of ethical developments in teleological terms – as progressing towards a fixed point. Fixed, that is, by the possibility conditions which delimit the best possible world, as known only to God. It would also force us to see ourselves as ethical beings which are fundamentally bound by historical contingencies in a broad sense, not open to a variety of possible ethical or social arrangements at any given time.

Author Image

By Luke DunneBA Philosophy & TheologyLuke is a graduate of the University of Oxford's departments of Philosophy and Theology, his main interests include the history of philosophy, the metaphysics of mind, and social theory.